[Skip to Content]
[Skip to Content Landing]

Where's the Value in Preoperative Covenants Between Surgeons and Patients?

Learning Objectives
1. Explain a new or unfamiliar viewpoint on a topic of ethical or professional conduct
2. Evaluate the usefulness of this information for health care practice, teaching, or conduct
3. Decide whether and when to apply the new information to health care practice, teaching, or conduct
1 Credit CME
Abstract

Values, preferences, and goals all affect patient autonomy. Their meanings are often conflated, so this article clarifies them and also distinguishes between hope and wish. Ethical investigation of preoperative and postoperative clinician–family communication in surgical intensive care units is needed to help mitigate value-incongruent, nonbeneficial operations and postoperative treatments as clinical scenarios unfold.

Communication as Covenant

Patients value having a sense of purpose, functional independence, meaningful interactions with family, spirituality, and avoiding burdening their loved ones.15 Surgeons are often more technique-oriented than people-oriented “fixers”68 who feel an intense sense of duty to their patients9,10 and strive for technical excellence.11 Preoperative communication in high-risk surgical scenarios has been described as a kind of covenant,12 with patients (and perhaps their loved ones) often assuming that a surgeon can fix any ailment and respond to complications13,14 and with surgeons assuming that patients agree to any postoperative surgical intensive care unit (SICU) interventions.5,1517 This article considers how continuing to see patient–surgeon communication as a covenant requires deeper ethical investigation into both surgeons' and patients' assumptions and into sources of dissonance between surgeons' and patients' values and goals.

The Nature of the Covenant

In his memoir, Do No Harm: Stories of Life, Death, and Brain Surgery, British neurosurgeon Henry Marsh states: “‘informed consent' sounds so easy in principle—the surgeon explains the … risks and benefits, and the calm and rational patient decides what he or she wants—just like … choosing from the vast array of toothbrushes on offer.” He continues: “The reality is very different. Patients are both terrified and ignorant … [and] will try to overcome their fear by investing the surgeon with superhuman abilities.”18 Here Marsh contrasts evidence-based reasoning, which he attributes only to surgeons, and a fear-based approach to decisions, which he attributes to patients. Marsh's characterization of surgeons as reasonable and patients as emotional might be too stark a contrast. Regardless, one ethical upshot is that, in most clinical encounters, information exchange in patient–surgeon communication is value laden on both sides and that the transformational potential of those values must be richly contextualized19 if informed consent is to be a process that expresses a surgeon's respect for a patient's autonomy20 and through which the covenantal nature of patient–surgeon communication can be upheld.

Keeping the Covenant

The actual process of respecting patient autonomy is messier than clinicians would like,20 devoid of neat risk calculations or tidy formulas for approaching clinician–patient communication,21 particularly when medical-surgical care pathway preferences are overshadowed by the enormous influence that existential fear has on human behavior and decision making.22 The high clinical and ethical stakes of postoperative SICU settings can intensify conscious and subconscious fears—of surgeons as well as families—regarding the implementation or foregoing of life-sustaining interventions and magnify the critical, life-or-death nature of these decisions.2,22 When patients' loved ones look to withdraw life-extending interventions, prioritize patients' comfort, or emphasize making their death as peaceful as possible, a surgeon might be reluctant to acquiesce.8,9,13,22Quiz Ref IDIn such cases, it is critical for surgeons to clearly distinguish between their own and their particular patient's values, preferences, and goals.23 The following working definitions can be helpful:

  • Quiz Ref IDValues can be understood as stable, fundamental meaning-based concepts (eg, ethical, aesthetic, spiritual) that have broad control over moral agents' (eg, surgeons', patients', patients' loved ones') motivations2,23 and actions.

  • Preferences can be understood as informed by values and as expressing moral agents' inclinations to prioritize one circumstance-specific course of action over another.

  • Goals can be understood as the objects, aims, or desired results that direct moral agents' preferred courses of action.2 Importantly, some goals are feasible, others are not.

In informed consent and all perioperative communication for surgical and palliative care, clarifying the suffering that patients are willing to endure for the possibility of achieving their goals24 is key to success, since many patients prefer their dying process not to be prolonged, especially if other values (ie, self-sufficiency, dignity, enjoyment, or comfort) are compromised.24,25

Falling Short

Physician and health care analyst David Eddy first applied a mathematical model to health decision making and concluded that 2 fundamental factors are (1) thoughtful analysis of evidence and (2) value judgments about risks and benefits of medical or surgical courses of action.26,27 Acceptable trade-offs (eg, willingness to extend life with specific procedures that will clearly diminish the quality of one's remaining time) and unacceptable burdens24,25 are also key features of informed consent and should be clarified, particularly when mortality risk is significant. Patients and their families value clear, compassionate communication that focuses on patients' preferences, goals, and values, as well as patient care that promotes comfort, dignity, and preservation of personhood.25,28 Yet, both preoperatively and postoperatively, surgeon–patient–family discussion is frequently inadequate for imagining end-of-life scenarios, much less for eliciting patients' values about meaning in life or how they might prefer to die.29,30 Physicians regularly fail to consider what matters most to patients. Even though spirituality is a highly prevalent value that becomes more pressing near the end of life,31,32 spiritual concerns are rarely addressed by clinicians when patients are in a critical condition.30,33 Moreover, when surrogates initiate religious or spiritual discussions in the ICU, the topic is frequently buried by clinicians, who might redirect conversations to medical considerations.33

Quiz Ref IDWell-meaning surgeons might mistakenly believe that when they lay out treatment options along with intervention-associated risk predictions they are respecting patient autonomy.34 This type of “independent informed choice,”3537 however, is seldom beneficent, nonmaleficent, or patient centered.38 As Ezekiel Emanuel and Linda Emanuel explain: “Freedom and control over medical decisions alone do not constitute patient autonomy.”35 True autonomy requires critical introspection on one's values prior to exercising one's freedom to act on those values.35 Furthermore, as Daniela Lamas and Lisa Rosenbaum note: “Patients may be asked to choose from a bewildering array of medical options.”37 Paradoxically, although freedom and autonomy might be logically thought to promote greater well-being, psychologist Barry Schwartz reminds us that such “choice overload” frequently does not lead to empowerment and emotional health, but rather to greater distress.39 In a recent and novel study undertaken by Leslie Scheunemann et al, family conferences rarely generated value-centered recommendations and fewer than half contained discussion of prolonged physical, cognitive, or emotional impairment among seriously ill patients.29 Soliciting appropriate surrogates' substituted judgment40,41 during family meetings can relieve survivors' guilt, anxiety, depression, and posttraumatic stress42,43 and mitigate complex grief,44,45 but substituted judgment conversations happened in only 13.5% of meetings that Scheunemann and colleagues analyzed.29

Values, preferences, and feasible goals—understood by all parties in the context of either acceptable trade-offs or unacceptable levels of suffering24,25—are needed for substituted judgment and shared decision making23,46 and are key to generating preoperative covenants and maintaining ongoing, collaborative postoperative communication in SICU settings as clinical scenarios unfold.2,30,47

Hope and Wish

As previously discussed, assumptions should be articulated and explicitly addressed in patient–surgeon communication; deeply held attitudes and beliefs about uncertain futures should, too. Surveyed cancer surgeons reported their most common ethical strivings were “providing patients with honest information without destroying hope” and “preserving patient choice.”48Quiz Ref IDWithholding honest (if not accurate) prognostic estimates, however, can deprive families of much-needed context and thwart planning, preventing families from focusing on what matters most to their loved one. Accuracy and realism are key features of trustworthy professionalism.49,50 In one study, 93% of 179 interviewed surrogate decision makers “felt that avoiding discussions about prognosis is an unacceptable way to maintain hope.”51Honest prognostic estimates also allow families a space for meaningful communication45 (eg, saying goodbye and expressing love, gratitude, and forgiveness).52 Because hope and wish—like values, preferences, and goals—are commonly conflated concepts that are often used to describe the value-laden future orientations and expectations of surgeons, patients, and their loved ones, another set of working definitions could help facilitate clear, covenantal communication.

  • Hope is a positive, empowering, transcendent attitude, which reveals the underpinnings of deep-meaning construction that are based on acceptance of realistic prognostication,32,5355 no matter how foreboding.

  • Quiz Ref IDWishes are distinctly more anxiety oriented and reality denying than hope, as they derive from imagined unrealistic outcomes or outcomes for which no feasible pathway exists.32

False hopes—such as patients' belief that if they die from surgery, they will do so peacefully in the operating room56 or beliefs that death itself can somehow be defeated—are therefore better termed wishes. False beliefs and fantastical wishes57 are commonly encountered in end-of-life scenarios—among both families58 and surgeons9,12,13,16,5961—and might upend ethical collaborative communication processes,57 particularly when grieving family members (and surgeons?) are asked to assess health information with realism and offer accurate preference-based substituted judgments.6264 True hope, paradoxically, is not outcome based, but rather transcends outcomes, as it is the meaning-based substratum of one's goals.32,53,55 As Balfour Mount, the father of palliative care states:

Hope is not the same as wishing. Hope is a perspective on reality, a point of view…. It reflects a degree of inner peace. Hope is a child of the human spirit. It arises from an experience of personal meaning. Wishing, however, arises from a sense of need, dissatisfaction and unrest. It reflects a sense of incompleteness. Hope is the product of adversity transcended, wishing of adversity denied.32

A Word About Wants

We caution against clinicians inquiring about what patients want, since, in our experience and the experience of other palliative care communication experts,65 this word prompts many patients and surrogates to think in terms of their wishes rather than in terms of their values, preferences, or realistic and meaningful goals. Value-congruent decisions require reflective—rather than reactive—thinking.1,20,46 Asking patients or surrogates whether they want surgery or want potentially value-discordant postoperative treatments, consistent with the “independent informed choice” communication style (what one noteworthy palliative care ethicist terms “radical autonomy”),41 can shift the decision-making power locus toward the patient41,48,65 even as it might invite the patient's immediate—and possibly fear-based—dichotomous decision65 rather than support the patient's reflection and deliberation about values1,14,23,29,36,45,48,6668 that can be expressed in a surgeon's patient-centered actions.

Overall, we suggest that surgeons looking to establish and nourish covenantal communication with their patients, especially preoperatively but also in SICU settings, do the following: identify surrogates early; clearly explain to surrogates what substituted judgment is and promote it by eliciting and helping to clarify patient values and preferences with all 3 parties; and articulate value-congruent care pathway recommendations while deliberating about why alternative paths are value incongruent or fantastical, along the lines we have suggested here. To facilitate patient-centered surgical care and good end-of-life contingency planning, we also suggest inviting patients and their surrogates to imagine and articulate unacceptable levels of suffering and possible acceptable death process scenarios before patients are incapacitated with operative anesthesia, postoperative sedation, or delirium or before they lose the ability to express their values in nuanced terms (eg, after intubation), particularly in high-risk cases. Creating and maintaining actionable, value-congruent, feasible, patient-focused action pathways is ethically and clinically necessary to making good on our covenants with those for whom we owe duties to care.

Sign in to take quiz and track your certificates

Our websites may be periodically unavailable between 7:00pm CT December 9, 2023 and 1:00am CT December 10, 2023 for regularly scheduled maintenance.

The AMA Journal of Ethics exists to help medical students, physicians and all health care professionals navigate ethical decisions in service to patients and society. The journal publishes cases and expert commentary, medical education articles, policy discussions, peer-reviewed articles for journal-based, video CME, audio CME, visuals, and more. Learn more

Article Information

AMA Journal of Ethics

AMA J Ethics. 2021;23(10):E814-822.

AMA CME Accreditation Information

Credit Designation Statement: The American Medical Association designates this journal-based CME activity for a maximum of 1.0 AMA PRA Category 1 Credit(s)™. Physicians should claim only the credit commensurate with the extent of their participation in the activity.

CME Disclosure Statement: Unless noted, all individuals in control of content reported no relevant financial relationships.

If applicable, all relevant financial relationships have been mitigated.

Conflict of Interest Disclosure: The author(s) had no conflicts of interest to disclose.

The viewpoints expressed in this article are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect the views and policies of the AMA.

Author Information:

  • Robert Ledbetter is a fourth-year medical student at Wake Forest University School of Medicine in Winston-Salem, North Carolina, and serves on the Public Relations Committee for Delivering Equal Access to Care Clinic, a student-run charitable medical clinic that provides high-quality care for local underserved communities. He received his BA degree in philosophy with a concentration in science and medicine from the University of Tennessee. His professional interests include emergency medicine as well as medical advocacy for equitable and just health care access for all; Buddy Marterre, MD, MDiv is an assistant professor of surgery and internal medicine at Wake Forest University School of Medicine in Winston-Salem, North Carolina, where he serves as co-director of the fourth-year medical student clinical clerkship in geriatrics and palliative care as well as the third-year clerkship in surgery and where he recently completed a master of divinity degree that included a hospital chaplaincy internship. He is a founding councilor of the Surgical Palliative Care Society.

References
1.
Scheunemann  LP, Arnold  RM, White  DB.  The facilitated values history: helping surrogates make authentic decisions for incapacitated patients with advanced illness.  Am J Respir Crit Care Med. 2012;186(6):480–486. Google ScholarCrossref
2.
Naik  AD, Martin  LA, Moye  J, Karel  MJ.  Health values and treatment goals of older, multimorbid adults facing life-threatening illness.  J Am Geriatr Soc. 2016;64(3):625–631. Google ScholarCrossref
3.
Steinhauser  KE, Christakis  NA, Clipp  EC, McNeilly  M, McIntyre  L, Tulsky  JA.  Factors considered important at the end of life by patients, family, physicians, and other care providers.  JAMA. 2000;284(19):2476–2482. Google ScholarCrossref
4.
Singer  PA, Martin  DK, Kelner  M.  Quality end-of-life care: patients' perspectives.  JAMA. 1999;281(2):163–168. Google ScholarCrossref
5.
Nabozny  MJ, Kruser  JM, Steffens  NM,  et al.  Patient-reported limitations to surgical buy-in: a qualitative study of patients facing high-risk surgery.  Ann Surg. 2017;265(1):97–102. Google ScholarCrossref
6.
Borges  NJ, Osmon  WR.  Personality and medical specialty choice: technique orientation versus people orientation.  J Vocat Behav. 2001;58(1):22–35. Google ScholarCrossref
7.
Kruser  JM, Pecanac  KE, Brasel  KJ,  et al.  “And I think that we can fix it”: mental models used in high-risk surgical decision making.  Ann Surg. 2015;261(4):678–684. Google ScholarCrossref
8.
Lee  CW, Vitous  CA, Silveira  MJ,  et al.  Delays in palliative care referral among surgical patients: perspectives of surgical residents across the state of Michigan.  J Pain Symptom Manage. 2019;57(6):1080–1088. Google ScholarCrossref
9.
Little  M.  The fivefold root of an ethics of surgery.  Bioethics. 2002;16(3):183–201. Google ScholarCrossref
10.
Angelos  P.  Responding to patient requests to withdraw life support: surgical ethics and responsibility.  Ann Surg. 2012;256(1):16–17. Google ScholarCrossref
11.
Katz  P.  The Scalpel's Edge: The Culture of Surgeons. Allyn & Bacon; 1999.
12.
Cassell  J, Buchman  TG, Streat  S, Stewart  RM.  Surgeons, intensivists, and the covenant of care: administrative models and values affecting care at the end of life-updated.  Crit Care Med. 2003;31(5):1551–1559. Google ScholarCrossref
13.
Buchman  TG, Cassell  J, Ray  SE.  Who should manage the dying patient?: rescue, shame, and the surgical ICU dilemma.  J Am Coll Surg. 2002;194(5):665–673. Google ScholarCrossref
14.
Schwarze  ML. 2019 John J. Conley Ethics and Philosophy Lecture: what we talk about when we talk about surgery.  American College of Surgeons. Accessed August 7, 2021. https://www.facs.org/education/academy/named-lectures/2019-conley
15.
Schwarze  ML, Redmann  AJ, Alexander  GC, Brasel  KJ.  Surgeons expect patients to buy-in to postoperative life support preoperatively: results of a national survey.  Crit Care Med. 2013;41(1):1–8. Google ScholarCrossref
16.
Schwarze  ML, Bradley  CT, Brasel  KJ.  Surgical “buy-in”: the contractual relationship between surgeons and patients that influences decisions regarding life-supporting therapy.  Crit Care Med. 2010;38(3):843–848. Google ScholarCrossref
17.
Pecanac  KE, Kehler  JM, Brasel  KJ,  et al.  It's big surgery: preoperative expressions of risk, responsibility, and commitment to treatment after high-risk operations.  Ann Surg. 2014;259(3):458–463. Google ScholarCrossref
18.
Marsh  H.  Do No Harm: Stories of Life, Death, and Brain Surgery. Thomas Dunne Books; 2015.
19.
Haidt  J.  The new synthesis in moral psychology.  Science. 2007;316(5827):998–1002. Google ScholarCrossref
20.
Fagan  A.  How autonomous is medical decision making?  AMA J Ethics. 2009;11(8):631–635. Google Scholar
21.
Morris  RS, Ruck  JM, Conca-Cheng  AM, Smith  TJ, Carver  TW, Johnston  FM.  Shared decision-making in acute surgical illness: the surgeon's perspective.  J Am Coll Surg. 2018;226(5):784–795. Google ScholarCrossref
22.
Solomon  S, Greenberg  J, Pyszczynski  T.  The Worm at the Core: On the Role of Death in Life. Penguin Random House; 2016.
23.
Baldt  B.  The influence of values in shared (medical) decision making.  Ethik Med. 2020;32(1):37–47. Google ScholarCrossref
24.
Gawande  A.  How to Talk End-of-Life Care With a Dying Patient. FORA.tv; 2010. Accessed January 29, 2019. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=45b2QZxDd_o
25.
Rubin  EB, Buehler  A, Halpern  SD.  Seriously ill patients' willingness to trade survival time to avoid high treatment intensity at the end of life.  JAMA Intern Med. 2020;180(6):907–909. Google ScholarCrossref
26.
Eddy  DM.  Anatomy of a decision.  JAMA. 1990;263(3):441–443. Google ScholarCrossref
27.
Tunis  SR.  Reflections on science, judgment, and value in evidence-based decision making: a conversation with David Eddy.  Health Aff (Millwood). 2007;26(4):w500–w515. Google Scholar
28.
Nelson  JE, Puntillo  KA, Pronovost  PJ,  et al.  In their own words: patients and families define high-quality palliative care in the intensive care unit.  Crit Care Med. 2010;38(3):808–818. Google ScholarCrossref
29.
Scheunemann  LP, Ernecoff  NC, Buddadhumaruk  P,  et al.  Clinician-family communication about patients' values and preferences in intensive care units.  JAMA Intern Med. 2019;179(5):676–684. Google ScholarCrossref
30.
Nabozny  MJ, Kruser  JM, Steffens  NM,  et al.  Constructing high-stakes surgical decisions: it's better to die trying.  Ann Surg. 2016;263(1):64–70. Google ScholarCrossref
31.
Balboni  TA, Balboni  MJ.  The spiritual event of serious illness.  J Pain Symptom Manage. 2018;56(5):816–822. Google ScholarCrossref
32.
Mount  BM.  Existential suffering and the determinants of healing.  Eur J Palliat Care. 2003;10(2)(suppl):40–42. Google Scholar
33.
Ernecoff  NC, Curlin  FA, Buddadhumaruk  P, White  DB.  Health care professionals' responses to religious or spiritual statements by surrogate decision makers during goals-of-care discussions.  JAMA Intern Med. 2015;175(10):1662–1669. Google ScholarCrossref
34.
Taylor  LJ, Johnson  SK, Nabozny  MJ,  et al.  Barriers to goal-concordant care for older patients with acute surgical illness: communication patterns extrinsic to decision aids.  Ann Surg. 2018;267(4):677–682. Google ScholarCrossref
35.
Emanuel  EJ, Emanuel  LL.  Four models of the physician-patient relationship.  JAMA. 1992;267(16):2221–2226. Google ScholarCrossref
36.
Quill  TE, Brody  H.  Physician recommendations and patient autonomy: finding a balance between physician power and patient choice.  Ann Intern Med. 1996;125(9):763–769. Google ScholarCrossref
37.
Lamas  D, Rosenbaum  L.  Freedom from the tyranny of choice—teaching the end-of-life conversation.  N Engl J Med. 2012;366(18):1655–1657. Google ScholarCrossref
38.
Joseph-Williams  N, Elwyn  G, Edwards  A.  Knowledge is not power for patients: a systematic review and thematic synthesis of patient-reported barriers and facilitators to shared decision making.  Patient Educ Couns. 2014;94(3):291–309. Google ScholarCrossref
39.
Schwartz  B.  Choice, freedom, and autonomy.  In: Shaver  PR, Mikulincer  M, eds.  Meaning, Mortality, and Choice: The Social Psychology of Existential Concerns. American Psychological Association; 2012:271–287. Google Scholar
40.
Buchanan  AE, Brock  DW.  Deciding for Others: The Ethics of Surrogate Decision Making. Cambridge University Press; 2008.
41.
Macauley  RC.  Ethics in Palliative Care: A Complete Guide. Oxford University Press; 2018.
42.
Pochard  F, Darmon  M, Fassier  T,  et al.  Symptoms of anxiety and depression in family members of intensive care unit patients before discharge or death. A prospective multicenter study.  J Crit Care. 2005;20(1):90–96. Google ScholarCrossref
43.
Azoulay  E, Pochard  F, Kentish-Barnes  N,  et al.  Risk of post-traumatic stress symptoms in family members of intensive care unit patients.  Am J Respir Crit Care Med. 2005;171(9):987–994. Google ScholarCrossref
44.
Tyrie  LS, Mosenthal  AC.  Care of the family in the surgical intensive care unit.  Surg Clin North Am. 2011;91(2):333–342. Google ScholarCrossref
45.
Otani  H, Yoshida  S, Morita  T,  et al.  Meaningful communication before death, but not present at the time of death itself, is associated with better outcomes on measures of depression and complicated grief among bereaved family members of cancer patients.  J Pain Symptom Manage. 2017;54(3):273–279. Google ScholarCrossref
46.
Légaré  F, Witteman  HO.  Shared decision making: examining key elements and barriers to adoption into routine clinical practice.  Health Aff (Millwood). 2013;32(2):276–284. Google ScholarCrossref
47.
Rubin  MA.  The collaborative autonomy model of medical decision-making.  Neurocrit Care. 2014;20(2):311–318. Google ScholarCrossref
48.
McCahill  LE, Krouse  RS, Chu  DZJ,  et al.  Decision making in palliative surgery.  J Am Coll Surg. 2002;195(3):411–422. Google ScholarCrossref
49.
Hagerty  RG, Butow  PN, Ellis  PM,  et al.  Communicating with realism and hope: incurable cancer patients' views on the disclosure of prognosis.  J Clin Oncol. 2005;23(6):1278–1288. Google ScholarCrossref
50.
Bernat  JL.  Ethical aspects of determining and communicating prognosis in critical care.  Neurocrit Care. 2004;1(1):107–117. Google ScholarCrossref
51.
Apatira  L, Boyd  EA, Malvar  G,  et al.  Hope, truth, and preparing for death: perspectives of surrogate decision makers.  Ann Intern Med. 2008;149(12):861–868. Google ScholarCrossref
52.
Byock  I.  The 4 Things That Matter Most. Canadian Virtual Hospice; 2011. Accessed January 1, 2019. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=vcMmx-6RIUY
53.
Feldman  DB, Snyder  CR.  Hope and the meaningful life: theoretical and empirical associations between goal-directed thinking and life meaning.  J Soc Clin Psychol. 2005;24(3):401–421. Google ScholarCrossref
54.
Eliott  JA, Olver  IN.  Hope and hoping in the talk of dying cancer patients.  Soc Sci Med. 2007;64(1):138–149. Google ScholarCrossref
55.
Dufault  K, Martocchio  BC.  Symposium on compassionate care and the dying experience. Hope: its spheres and dimensions.  Nurs Clin North Am. 1985;20(2):379–391. Google Scholar
56.
Nabozny  MJ, Kruser  JM, Steffens  NM,  et al.  Constructing high-stakes surgical decisions: it's better to die trying.  Ann Surg. 2016;263(1):64–70. Google ScholarCrossref
57.
Chaet  DH.  AMA Code of Medical Ethics' opinions related to false beliefs in health care.  AMA J Ethics. 2018;20(11):1049–1051. Google Scholar
58.
Zier  LS, Burack  JH, Micco  G, Chipman  AK, Frank  JA, White  DB.  Surrogate decision makers' responses to physicians' predictions of medical futility.  Chest. 2009;136(1):110–117. Google ScholarCrossref
59.
Olson  TJP, Brasel  KJ, Redmann  AJ, Alexander  GC, Schwarze  ML.  Surgeon-reported conflict with intensivists about postoperative goals of care.  JAMA Surg. 2013;148(1):29–35. Google ScholarCrossref
60.
Olson  TJP, Schwarze  ML.  Failure-to-pursue rescue: truly a failure?  Ann Surg. 2015;262(2):e43–e44. Google ScholarCrossref
61.
Sorella  MC, Sakakushev  B, Coccolini  F,  et al.  Ethical decisions and dilemmas in the ACS patients requiring ICU: understanding when to start and when to stop.  In: Picetti  E, Pereira  BM, Razek  T, Narayan  M, Kashuk  JL, eds.  Intensive Care for Emergency Surgeons. Springer International Publishing; 2019:321–329. Google Scholar
62.
Sulmasy  DP, Terry  PB, Weisman  CS,  et al.  The accuracy of substituted judgments in patients with terminal diagnoses.  Ann Intern Med. 1998;128(8):621–629. Google ScholarCrossref
63.
Shalowitz  DI, Garrett-Mayer  E, Wendler  D.  The accuracy of surrogate decision makers: a systematic review.  Arch Intern Med. 2006;166(5):493–497. Google ScholarCrossref
64.
Fagerlin  A, Ditto  PH, Danks  JH, Houts  RM, Smucker  WD.  Projection in surrogate decisions about life-sustaining medical treatments.  Health Psychol. 2001;20(3):166–175. Google ScholarCrossref
65.
Schwarze  ML, Campbell  TC, Cunningham  TV, White  DB, Arnold  RM.  You can't get what you want: innovation for end-of-life communication in the intensive care unit.  Am J Respir Crit Care Med. 2016;193(1):14–16. Google ScholarCrossref
66.
Abhyankar  P, Bekker  HL, Summers  BA, Velikova  G.  Why values elicitation techniques enable people to make informed decisions about cancer trial participation.  Health Expect. 2011;14(suppl 1):20–32. Google Scholar
67.
Marterre  B, Shin  J, Terzian  WTH.  Shared decision-making in the context of uncertain care goals and outcomes: dissecting a penetrating abdominal trauma case complicated by enterocutaneous fistulae.  Am Surg. 2020;86(11):1456–1461. Google ScholarCrossref
68.
Cooper  Z, Courtwright  A, Karlage  A, Gawande  A, Block  S.  Pitfalls in communication that lead to nonbeneficial emergency surgery in elderly patients with serious illness: description of the problem and elements of a solution.  Ann Surg. 2014;260(6):949–957. Google ScholarCrossref
AMA CME Accreditation Information

Credit Designation Statement: The American Medical Association designates this Journal-based CME activity activity for a maximum of 1.00  AMA PRA Category 1 Credit(s)™. Physicians should claim only the credit commensurate with the extent of their participation in the activity.

Successful completion of this CME activity, which includes participation in the evaluation component, enables the participant to earn up to:

  • 1.00 Medical Knowledge MOC points in the American Board of Internal Medicine's (ABIM) Maintenance of Certification (MOC) program;;
  • 1.00 Self-Assessment points in the American Board of Otolaryngology – Head and Neck Surgery’s (ABOHNS) Continuing Certification program;
  • 1.00 MOC points in the American Board of Pediatrics’ (ABP) Maintenance of Certification (MOC) program;
  • 1.00 Lifelong Learning points in the American Board of Pathology’s (ABPath) Continuing Certification program; and
  • 1.00 credit toward the CME of the American Board of Surgery’s Continuous Certification program

It is the CME activity provider's responsibility to submit participant completion information to ACCME for the purpose of granting MOC credit.

Close
Close
Close
Close

Name Your Search

Save Search
Close
Close

Lookup An Activity

or

My Saved Searches

You currently have no searches saved.

Close

My Saved Courses

You currently have no courses saved.

Close