[Skip to Content]
[Skip to Content Landing]

How Should Clinicians Navigate Decision Making About Genital Reconstructive Surgeries Among Intersex and Transgender Populations?

Learning Objectives
1. Explain a new or unfamiliar viewpoint on a topic of ethical or professional conduct
2. Evaluate the usefulness of this information for health care practice, teaching, or conduct
3. Decide whether and when to apply the new information to health care practice, teaching, or conduct
1 Credit CME
Abstract

Genital reconstructive surgeries (GRS) are available for a variety of indications and populations, including transgender and gender diverse (TGD) individuals and those with intersex traits/differences in sex development (I/dsd). Despite the common outcomes of GRS for TGD and I/dsd individuals, decision making about this surgical care differs between these populations and across the lifespan. Sociocultural perspectives on sexuality and gender dominate the ethics of GRS, and reform is needed within clinical ethics to center the autonomy of TGD and I/dsd individuals in informed consent processes. Such changes are necessary to ensure justice in health care for all sex and gender diverse individuals across the lifespan.

Introduction

For transgender and gender diverse (TGD) individuals and for those with intersex traits/differences in sex development (I/dsd)—an umbrella term used to describe a constellation of congenital variations in sex traits—genital reconstructive surgeries (GRS) have analogous aesthetic and functional outcomes that contribute to sexual, gender, and reproductive health.1,2Quiz Ref IDCandidacy for GRS among sex and gender diverse populations has historically varied based on age. GRS for TGD populations is primarily accessible to adults, usually those who have reached the legal age of majority.1 In contrast, individuals with I/dsd are often considered for GRS in infancy and childhood.3 The ethics of decision making about GRS in these respective populations has evolved in parallel with clinical norms, such that considerations of beneficence and nonmaleficence in GRS—which are steeped in dominant societal notions of sexuality and gender—supersede considerations of respect for autonomy and justice.

After describing sociocultural norms of sexuality and gender, we examine historical and contemporary ethics of decision making about GRS that are influenced by these norms. Based on our collective history and extensive discussions with clinicians, community members, and advocates, we assert that GRS across the lifespan is ethically sound when the autonomy of sex and gender diverse individuals is centered in decision making and when these individuals are active participants in informed consent processes. We also identify and problematize divergent approaches to informed consent that do not consistently empower sex- and gender-diverse individuals as decision makers—either in adulthood or in adolescence, a period in the lifespan when both TGD individuals and those with I/dsd may seek GRS.

Influence of Sociocultural Norms on GRS

Quiz Ref IDSociocultural norms about sexuality and gender in the United States inform “standard” expectations for GRS procedures and associated surgical goals and outcomes. For example, people with 46 XX chromosomes who have virilizing congenital adrenal hyperplasia (CAH) are routinely considered for clitoral recession procedures because they have female sex organs (ovaries, uterus, and vagina) and gender identity (often reared from birth as female). Clinicians are less likely to expect that these patients will want metoidioplasty and urethral lengthening to create a more prominent phallus. It is assumed in these cases that societal norms and individual preferences will favor external genitalia typical of an endosex female (whose sexual traits are aligned with what is expected of “female” sexed bodies). We use the term endosex and explicitly name the majority category to avoid the implicit othering of minority individuals that occurs when framing minority status as being in opposition to “normal.”

Notably, there is some evidence that girls with virilizing CAH are more likely to identify as non-cisgender than girls without CAH and that some 46,XX CAH children may do well when raised male.4 As such, the threshold for parental consent for GRS to “correct” I/dsd variations—typically, for clitoroplasty in a child with CAH—is lower than the threshold for parental consent for GRS to affirm gender identity—eg, for metoidioplasty in an adolescent with CAH—because the former aligns with normative societal expectations, while the latter does not. As a result of such norms, TGD individuals across the lifespan also encounter clinicians who are hesitant or reticent to perform GRS when projected surgical outcomes do not aesthetically or functionally align with binary endosex standards. For example, vaginal sparing phalloplasty is a “nonstandard” GRS procedure that creates a phallus and preserves a functional vagina.

Historical and Medical Context for GRS

I/dsd populations. It is estimated that individuals with I/dsd compose up to 2% of the global population.5 GRS in individuals with I/dsd is medically indicated to treat or normalize genital aesthetic and functional variance.2 For example, urogenital sinus mobilization separates urethral and vaginal openings to achieve average, endosex female anatomical genital appearance and to promote future sexual and reproductive capacity, including tampon insertion, penile-vaginal intercourse with effective insemination, and the capacity for vaginal delivery.6 Originating in the 1930s, GRS for individuals with I/dsd made possible the alteration of infants' genitals in order to align their gross anatomy and functionality with that of endosex individuals' genitalia.7 Throughout the history of GRS for individuals with I/dsd, medical and ethics academies have endorsed—and clinicians have consistently upheld—guardians as the most appropriate decision makers regarding their children's sexual, gender, and reproductive health.7 Prevailing ethical norms and legal standards continue to empower guardians to decide for or against infant or childhood GRS for individuals with I/dsd.

Since the 1990s, some individuals with I/dsd have shared lived experiences of early GRS as negatively affecting their sexual function and reproductive potential.8 These stakeholders have also voiced concerns about genital anatomical modifications in infancy or early childhood that could conflict with an individual's future gender identity and embodiment goals.8Quiz Ref IDTheir advocacy has invoked the principle of respect for autonomy and the right to an open future—the right of the child to self-determination, including the ability, upon achieving maturity, to make decisions about gender identity, sexual anatomy, and sexual and reproductive function—as guideposts of ethical decision making about GRS. Accordingly, clinicians and guardians in contemporary US health care settings have been called upon to postpone GRS until individuals with I/dsd can participate in informed consent processes.9 However, GRS in infancy and early childhood remains the standard of care for I/dsd populations at most US medical institutions.2

TGD populations. While global prevalence estimates are difficult to establish, TGD individuals compose around 0.6% of the US population, although the percentage is higher among adolescents (1.4%).10 Up to two-thirds of members of the TGD population in the United States may, during their lifetime, desire GRS to treat or relieve gender incongruence or dysphoria—distress arising from a mismatch between their gender and their sense of their physical, psychological, and emotional self.11 In its nascence, GRS for TGD individuals encompassed procedures common to GRS for individuals with I/dsd but the procedures were performed only on adults. Initial surgeries modified postpubertal genital anatomy according to aesthetic standards of endosex individuals of the “opposite” sex, and therefore surgical outcomes achieved select aspects of genital functionality per standards of heterosexuality.12 Despite differing medical indications, GRS in TGD and I/dsd populations shared similar periprocedural complications and postprocedural sequelae related to fertility and sexual function.1,3

Historically, TGD individuals received nominal direction from clinicians regarding medical interventions of relevance to their sexual, gender, and reproductive health and thus sought GRS at their own discretion.13,14 In contrast to candidacy for GRS for individuals with I/dsd, eligibility for GRS for TGD individuals was often contingent on presurgical psychological evaluations intended to assess TGD individuals' readiness for GRS and to protect clinicians from ethical and legal scrutiny. This legacy reverberates in contemporary insurance and institutional requirements for GRS for TGD individuals in the United States.1,12,15 Notably, GRS is not widely accessible to TGD individuals in the United States before the legal age of majority, even with guardians' consent.16 This age-related criterion for GRS reflects the international gold standard for TGD medical care set by the World Professional Association of Transgender Health (WPATH), which specified, until its most recent guidance update in 2022,17 that GRS should not be undertaken until the age of majority in any given country and, unlike with chest surgeries, WPATH did not provide alternate eligibility criteria for adolescents.1

Inconsistencies in Decision Making

Informed consent manifests the ethical principle of respect for an individual's autonomy in decision making about medical care; upholds personal values of self-determination, sovereignty, authenticity, and best interest; and realizes intentional, collective, and relational decision making among individuals and other stakeholders.18 While clinicians are habitual stakeholders, guardians become stakeholders when individuals do not meet legal and clinical standards of competence and capacity. Importantly, in childhood and adolescence, guardians are stakeholders with legal authority to make decisions for the child,19,20 which is relevant to the ways in which decision making about GRS occurs for individuals with I/dsd.

I/dsd populations.Quiz Ref IDBecause GRS for individuals with I/dsd is most often performed in infancy and early childhood when the future preferences of individuals with I/dsd are unknowable, the locus of informed consent is the guardian. At this life stage, an individual with I/dsd's assent is unobtainable. Neither legal competence nor decision-making capacity are present. As such, guardians rely upon their own values, those of clinicians, and the perceived values of society writ large to make a decision about GRS that they believe is in the best interest of the individual with I/dsd. In the context of clinical counseling, these stakeholders may be influenced by assumptions not associated with high-quality scientific evidence—specifically, the assumption that children with endosex genitalia will have better psychosocial outcomes than children with intersex genitalia in maturity.7 In addition, decisions about surgery may reflect culturally determined assumptions, including that a child with I/dsd will mature as heterosexual and desire aesthetically and functionally normative genitalia. Acceptance of a right to an open future prioritizes the as-yet-unknown values of an individual with I/dsd during childhood and can guide the guardian's determination of the individual's best interest regarding early GRS.19

TGD populations. In contrast to individuals with I/dsd, TGD individuals are central to decision making about GRS. Legal competence, as primarily defined by attainment of the legal age of majority, is ethically requisite. Consequently, informed consent for GRS most often occurs during adulthood, and the individual's preferences and conception of quality of life are considered essential but insufficient for informed consent. Many clinicians and Global North societies view age as a proxy for psychological and cognitive maturity and dispute TGD adolescents' ability to conceptualize their preferences about GRS.1,20,21 As such, societal obligation to the welfare of children is often considered to preclude GRS for TGD adolescents, even if they seek to assent and consent is given by their guardian(s). Importantly, many TGD adolescents have a strong sense of self-determination, authenticity, and their own best interest, although these values are rarely given substantive consideration or factored into professional guidelines concerning decision making about GRS for TGD adolescents.20

Despite the growing acceptance of gender diversity in Global North societies, ethical standards for decision making about GRS continue to incorporate the assumption that TGD individuals' original genitalia are “normal” and “healthy” and to posit regret as a significant risk of surgery.17 Psychological evaluations are often required to corroborate an individual's preferences and decision-making capacity, an insurance- and clinician-driven criterion that TGD and medical advocates identify as excessively restrictive and medically unnecessary.21 Desired genital alterations in GRS are diverse (see Table), and individuals whose preferences do not align with binary endosex norms can also experience regret if they do not undergo GRS.22

Table. Examples of GRS in I/dsd and TGD Populations

ProcedureUsed in I/dsdaUsed in TGDaEffects on Fertility
ClitoroplastyYesYesNone
GonadectomybYesYesRemoval is sterilizing if gonads are functional
HysterectomyYesYesSterilizing
Excision of mullerian remnantsbYesYesRisk of impaired fertility
LabiaplastyYesYesNone
PenectomyNoYesNone
PhalloplastyNoYesNone
ScrotoplastyNoYesNone
Urethral lengthening or shorteningYesYesLengthening may facilitate penile-vaginal sex if performed in a sperm-producing individual with I/dsdc
Urogenital sinus mobilizationYesNoMay address issues that affect fertility of individual with I/dsd during penile-vaginal sexc
VaginectomyNoYesNone
VaginoplastyYesYesSterilizing if testes of TGD individuals removed; may address obstructive issues that affect fertility of I/dsd individuals during penile-vaginal sexc

Quiz Ref IDAs of February 2023, 28 US state governments have introduced or passed legislation banning GRS and other gender-affirming care for TGD minors, even with guardian consent.23 In some states, this legislation subjects to criminal liability any clinicians who provide GRS or guardians who consent to such care for TGD adolescents.23,24 While eliminating the rights of guardians of TGD adolescents to consent to GRS actively desired and sought by their minor offspring, these mandates often incorporate explicit GRS exemptions for guardians of I/dsd infants and children and tacit permission for gender-affirming care among cisgender adolescents, such as breast augmentation or gynecomastia repair, with guardian consent.25 Such laws and policies reify an “ethics of normativity” in decision making about GRS. They also empower state governments as an implicit stakeholder, one with autonomy disproportionate to that entrusted to individuals, clinicians, and guardians and that tends to enforce sexual and gender uniformity as defined by dominant Global North societies.7 An ethics of normativity undermines respect for autonomy and defines beneficence and nonmaleficence solely in terms of the expectations of these societies. This reality precludes ethically sound informed consent for GRS in adolescence.

Working With I/dsd and TGD Populations

We recommend reform of clinical ethics to prioritize the autonomy of TGD adolescents and those with I/dsd irrespective of dominant sociocultural expectations regarding GRS. We propose the following key considerations to guide decision making and practice:

  1. GRS must be considered within an ethical context that understands sex and gender diversity to be normal, not pathological, states. Within such a decision-making framework, clinicians and other stakeholders champion the autonomy of TGD youth and those with I/dsd by emphasizing their self-determination, sovereignty, authenticity, and best interest. Ethically sound informed consent for GRS—especially concerning the rights of guardians to consent to these procedures for children and adolescents—warrants that the individuals who would be undergoing the procedure be considered active stakeholders and that their rights be given precedence when appropriate, based on their decisional capacity.

  2. The right to an open future must be prioritized in decision making about GRS for children and adolescents. Reproductive and sexual health are universal human rights.26 Decisions about fertility and sexuality are to be driven, to the extent possible, by the individuals that they most directly affect. Furthermore, all GRS must explicitly direct their primary benefit to the individual, as opposed to the guardian, the clinician, or other stakeholders.

  3. Assessment of adolescents' decisional capacity using best practices is imperative to decision making about GRS for adolescents.27

Health care justice for TGD individuals and those with I/dsd requires explicit acknowledgment of dominant societal expectations so that they may be intentionally factored into decision making. Within this evolved ethics of GRS, justice is promoted by centering respect for the individual's autonomy in decision making, seeing beneficence and nonmaleficence as principles that must derive from the locus of individual autonomy, and prioritizing the present and future rights of the individual over those of other implicit and explicit stakeholders.

Sign in to take quiz and track your certificates

The AMA Journal of Ethics exists to help medical students, physicians and all health care professionals navigate ethical decisions in service to patients and society. The journal publishes cases and expert commentary, medical education articles, policy discussions, peer-reviewed articles for journal-based, video CME, audio CME, visuals, and more. Learn more

Article Information

AMA Journal of Ethics

AMA J Ethics. 2023;25(6):E437-445

AMA CME Accreditation Information

Credit Designation Statement: The American Medical Association designates this journal-based CME activity for a maximum of 1 AMA PRA Category 1 Credit(s)™. Physicians should claim only the credit commensurate with the extent of their participation in the activity.

Disclosure Statement: Unless noted, all individuals in control of content reported no relevant financial relationships.

If applicable, all relevant financial relationships have been mitigated.

Conflict of Interest Disclosure: Elizabeth R. Boskey serves on the Advisory Council of the Planned Parenthood ASPIRE (Advancing Science and Practice Through Innovations in Research and Education) Center for Sexual and Reproductive Health and until recently served as the expert on sexual and gender health at Verywell Health. Co-authors listed no activities or interests as conflicts to disclose.

The viewpoints expressed in this article are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect the views and policies of the AMA.

Author Information:

  • Frances Grimstad, MD, MS is a pediatric and adolescent gynecologist at Boston Children's Hospital in Massachusetts who works with patients with intersex traits/differences of sex development and transgender and gender diverse patients. She is also an assistant professor of obstetrics, gynecology, and reproductive biology at Harvard Medical School; Jessica Kremen, MD is a pediatric endocrinologist at Boston Children's Hospital in Massachusetts who works with intersex and transgender and gender diverse patients; Elizabeth R. Boskey, PhD, MPH, LICSW is a scientist in the Division of Gynecology at Boston Children's Hospital in Massachusetts and works with sexual and gender minority individuals and couples in private practice. Dr Boskey completed the Harvard Medical School Fellowship in Bioethics in 2019 with a capstone project on reproductive ethics for TGD adolescents; Hannah Wenger, MD is a settler physician at the Northwest Portland Area Indian Health Board in Oregon and at Penn State Health. Her areas of clinical interest are Indigenous health, gender care, and clinical ethics.

References:
1.
Coleman  E, Bockting  W, Botzer  M,  et al.  Standards of Care for the Health of Transsexual, Transgender, and Gender-Nonconforming People, version 7.  Int J Transgend. 2012;13(4):165–232.Google ScholarCrossref
2.
Lee  PA, Nordenström  A, Houk  CP,  et al.  Global disorders of sex development update since 2006: perceptions, approach and care.  Horm Res Paediatr. 2016;85(3):158–180.Google ScholarCrossref
3.
Lee  PA, Houk  CP, Ahmed  SF, Hughes  IA.  Consensus statement on management of intersex disorders.  Pediatrics. 2006;118(2):e488–e500.Google ScholarCrossref
4.
Pasterski  V, Zucker  KJ, Hindmarsh  PC,  et al.  Increased cross-gender identification independent of gender role behavior in girls with congenital adrenal hyperplasia: results from a standardized assessment of 4- to 11-year-old children.  Arch Sex Behav. 2015;44(5):1363–1375.Google ScholarCrossref
5.
Blackless  M, Charuvastra  A, Derryck  A, Fausto-Sterling  A, Lauzanne  K, Lee  E.  How sexually dimorphic are we? Review and synthesis.  Am J Hum Biol. 2000;12(2):151–166.Google ScholarCrossref
6.
Jesus  VM, Buriti  F, Lessa  R, Toralles  MB, Oliveira  LB, Barroso  U.  Total urogenital sinus mobilization for ambiguous genitalia.  J Pediatr Surg. 2018;53(4):808–812.Google ScholarCrossref
7.
Reis  E.  Bodies in Doubt: An American History of Intersex. Johns Hopkins University Press; 2012.
8.
Karkazis  K.  Fixing Sex: Intersex, Medical Authority, and Lived Experience. Duke University Press; 2008.
9.
Sandberg  DE, Vilain  E.  Decision making in differences of sex development/intersex care in the USA: bridging advocacy and family-centred care.  Lancet Diabetes Endocrinol. 2022;10(6):381–383.Google ScholarCrossref
10.
Herman  JL, Flores  AR, O'Neill  KK.  How Many Adults and Youth Identify as Transgender in the United States? UCLA School of Law; 2022. Accessed July 24, 2022. https://williamsinstitute.law.ucla.edu/publications/trans-adults-united-states/
11.
James  SE, Herman  JL, Keisling  M, Mottet  L, Anafi  M.  The Report of the 2015 US Transgender Survey. National Center for Transgender Equality; 2016. Accessed April 18, 2023. https://transequality.org/sites/default/files/docs/usts/USTS-Full-Report-Dec17.pdf
12.
Stryker  S.  Transgender History: The Roots of Today’s Revolution.. Seal Press; 2008.
13.
Willis  P, Dobbs  C, Evans  E, Raithby  M, Bishop  JA.  Reluctant educators and self-advocates: older trans adults' experiences of health-care services and practitioners in seeking gender-affirming services.  Health Expect. 2020;23(5):1231–1240.Google ScholarCrossref
14.
Dawson  R, Leong  T.  Not up for debate: LGBTQ people need and deserve tailored sexual and reproductive health care.  Guttmacher Institute; November16 , 2020. Accessed July 24, 2022. https://www.guttmacher.org/article/2020/11/not-debate-lgbtq-people-need-and-deserve-tailored-sexual-and-reproductive-health
15.
Almazan  AN, Benson  TA, Boskey  ER, Ganor  O.  Associations between transgender exclusion prohibitions and insurance coverage of gender-affirming surgery.  LGBT Health. 2020;7(5):254–263.Google ScholarCrossref
16.
Milrod  C, Karasic  DH.  Age is just a number: WPATH-affiliated surgeons' experiences and attitudes toward vaginoplasty in transgender females under 18 years of age in the United States.  J Sex Med. 2017;14(4):624–634.Google ScholarCrossref
17.
Coleman  E, Radix  AE, Bouman  WP,  et al.  Standards of Care for the Health of Transgender and Gender Diverse People, version 8.  Int J Transgend Health. 2022;23(suppl 1):S1–S259.Google Scholar
18.
Wendler  D.  Promoting the values for surrogate decision-making.  JAMA. 2022;328(3):243–244.Google ScholarCrossref
19.
Bangalore Krishna  K, Kogan  BA, Mazur  T, Hoebeke  P, Bogaert  G, Lee  PA.  Individualized care for patients with intersex (differences of sex development): part 4/5. Considering the ifs, whens, and whats regarding sexual-reproductive system surgery.  J Pediatr Urol. 2021;17(3):338–345.Google ScholarCrossref
20.
Kimberly  L, McBride Folkers  K, Karrington  B, Wernick  J, Busa  S, Salas-Humara  C.  Navigating evolving ethical questions in decision making for gender-affirming medical care for adolescents.  J Clin Ethics. 2021;32(4):307–321.Google ScholarCrossref
21.
Cavanaugh  T, Hopwood  R, Lambert  C.  Informed consent in the medical care of transgender and gender-nonconforming patients.  AMA J Ethics. 2016;18(11):1147–1155.Google Scholar
22.
Hopwood  RA.  Supporting the transgender individual in deciding their pathway.  In: Kauth  MR, Shipherd  JC, eds.  Adult Transgender Care: An Interdisciplinary Approach for Training Mental Health Professionals. Routledge; 2018:61–77.Google Scholar
23.
Goodwin  GE.  Utah just banned gender-affirming healthcare for transgender kids. These 21 other states are considering similar bills in 2023.  Insider. February 1 , 2023. Accessed February 23, 2023. https://www.insider.com/states-considering-bills-ban-gender-affirming-healthcare-transgender-youth-2023-1Google Scholar
24.
Dawson  L, Kates  J.  Youth access to gender-affirming care: the federal and state policy landscape.  Kaiser Family Foundation. June 1 , 2022. Accessed February 23, 2023. https://www.kff.org/other/issue-brief/youth-access-to-gender-affirming-care-the-federal-and-state-policy-landscape/
25.
 Outlawing trans youth: state legislatures and the battle over gender-affirming healthcare for minors.  Harv Law Rev. 2021;134(6):2163–2185. Accessed February 23, 2023. https://harvardlawreview.org/wp-content/uploads/2021/04/134-Harv.-L.-Rev.-2163.pdfGoogle Scholar
26.
Human Reproduction Programme.  Sexual Health, Human Rights and the Law. World Health Organization; 2015. Accessed February 23, 2023. https://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/handle/10665/175556/9789241564984_eng.pdf
27.
Baltag  V, Takeuchi  Y, Guthold  R, Ambresin  AE.  Assessing and supporting adolescents' capacity for autonomous decision-making in health-care settings: new guidance from the World Health Organization.  J Adolesc Health. 2022;71(1):10–13.Google ScholarCrossref
AMA CME Accreditation Information

Credit Designation Statement: The American Medical Association designates this Journal-based CME activity activity for a maximum of 1.00  AMA PRA Category 1 Credit(s)™. Physicians should claim only the credit commensurate with the extent of their participation in the activity.

Successful completion of this CME activity, which includes participation in the evaluation component, enables the participant to earn up to:

  • 1.00 Medical Knowledge MOC points in the American Board of Internal Medicine's (ABIM) Maintenance of Certification (MOC) program;;
  • 1.00 Self-Assessment points in the American Board of Otolaryngology – Head and Neck Surgery’s (ABOHNS) Continuing Certification program;
  • 1.00 MOC points in the American Board of Pediatrics’ (ABP) Maintenance of Certification (MOC) program;
  • 1.00 Lifelong Learning points in the American Board of Pathology’s (ABPath) Continuing Certification program; and
  • 1.00 credit toward the CME [and Self-Assessment requirements] of the American Board of Surgery’s Continuous Certification program

It is the CME activity provider's responsibility to submit participant completion information to ACCME for the purpose of granting MOC credit.

Close
Close
Close
Close

Name Your Search

Save Search
Close
Close

Lookup An Activity

or

My Saved Searches

You currently have no searches saved.

Close

My Saved Courses

You currently have no courses saved.

Close